Sunday, November 27, 2011

Basis for The Republic


Justice has the following characteristics:  
1.      Happiness: As Socrates established when rebuking Thrasymachus’ proposal of justice, justice inevitably leads to happiness because he states “the just mind and the just man will have a good life” (Book I, 353e) and “the man who has a good life is prosperous and happy.” (Book I, 353e) Therefore, doing right allows a man to lead a good life and be happy with it.
Unity: Socrates states that injustice leads to disunity of purpose because when people commit wrongdoings within a group, the end result is enmity and anarchy. “But if they treat each other justly, there will be unity and purpose and friendly feeling among them,” (Book I, 351d) says Socrates.
Strength: Following his belief that justice creates unity, Socrates argues justice creates strength of the individual and society. He argues that an unjust group is incapable of any common action, thus the group is weak, and the individual becomes weak because he is preoccupied by the group’s internal strife.
Wisdom: Socrates states, “…intelligence is good, lack of it bad.” (Book I, 349e) Socrates establishes that a man with professional knowledge is wise and a wise man is good and a good man does not compete with his fellows, only with his opposite. Thus, Socrates illustrates that the just are wise.
Excellence: The mind, like any other thing, has a function and the ability to operate well or badly. Therefore, like any other thing, the mind has a “peculiar excellence” (Book I, 353e). Socrates states that justice is the excellence of the mind while injustice is the mind’s defect. Socrates values excellence on par with wisdom and justice.
Peace: Socrates criticizes Polemarchus’ definition of justice and in the process emphasizes that it is “not the function of the just man to harm either his friends or anyone else.” (Book I, 335d) Therefore, just men do not harm others which highlights that Socrates believes justice requires peace.

2.      After establishing that justice, like medicine, is a skill, Socrates continues that justice is the “skill that enables us to help and injure one’s friends and enemies.” (Book I, 332b) Socrates questions when justice is useful in society, which Polemarchus consequently answers when things are to be kept safe. Socrates turns this statement around by establishing those “good at keeping a thing will be good at stealing it.” (Book I, 333c) Thus, Socrates tackles Polemarchus’ initial assumption that justice is a matter of giving every man his due by proposing justice is a kind of stealing even though it is used to help a friend and harm an enemy. Furthermore, Socrates, after having Polemarchus agree that we ought to give both our friends and our enemies their due, argues that doing good for your friends and harm to your enemies is difficult without knowing the meaning of friends and enemies. There are those who seem honest when they actually are not, and thus it is possible for men to “injure their friends, who in their eyes are bad, and help their enemies, who are good.” (Book I, 334e) Changing the definition of friends and enemies to those who seem and are respectively good and evil, Socrates changes the definition of justice to doing good for friends who are good, and harm to enemies who are evil. Socrates then argues that harming creates a man more unjust and just men will not use their justice to make others unjust and therefore just and good men do not harm others, even enemies, but the opposite. Polemarchus’ position is defeated at this point because Socrates questioned the very meaning of friends and enemies, justice, and the purpose of a just man, to which Polemarchus had no objections.
         I do agree that these admissions lead Polemarchus to doubt his own position and thus are fatal to his previous position. I do agree with Socrates’ conclusion that the function of a good and just man is to help, not harm. Also, I do not agree that justice is a type of skill; instead, I believe justice is dependent upon one’s actions and their moral implications within a society. Following, I do not believe that justice can be improved upon like a skill for one’s actions are determined by one’s own morals, which can change but not be improved upon.

3.      Thrasymachus held firm that the pursuit of self-interest or injustice pays better than justice does. Following, Socrates established that the “just man does not compete with his like, but only his unlike, while the unjust man competes with both like and unlike.” (Book I, 349d-e) Socrates then followed with the precise definition of a professional man that the professional, good, and just man does not compete with his fellows, however, an unjust and ignorant man without intelligence competes with his those like and unlike him. Thus, Socrates undermines Thrasymachus’ statement that injustice is wise and excellent, while justice is the opposite. Socrates’ criticism of this point was rather weak because he drew from assumptions; after all, who is to say that the just and wise man does not compete with his fellows to be better at the job than others. Students, for example, go through a competitive process at medical school in order to become doctors. Students who put more work and effort in the job often become doctors and those who do not put effort into their work do not become doctors. Therefore, students must compete, even if by doing so they are working to benefit the patients. I do not think there is anything bad or unwise about competition, in fact, competition drives professional workers to do their jobs better. Competition is not the sign of the bad and ignorant as long as all rules are followed and it does not turn malicious.
          Socrates further argued Thrasymachus’ point by giving the example of a society, group, or army. In the case of injustice, men within the group would be causing wrongdoings to each other and therefore fostering disunity and weakness. Thus, he follows that in order to have unity and effective joint action between men, the men of the group must act justly towards each other. This section of Socrates’ criticism is enjoyably concise and accurate and therefore is effective in tearing down Thrasymachus’ view that injustice is a sign of strength. Thrasymachus stated that injustice is a sign of strength in the case of the individual, but Socrates applied injustice to a society and illustrated how impractical it is for all people within a group to act unjustly. Thus, justice is actually the sign of a strong society. I agree with Socrates’ criticism of this point, however, I wish he addressed injustice on the individual level as that was Thrasymachus’ original point. Personally, I think justice cannot be applied to the individual because the definition and maintenance of justice must be decided upon and enforced by a society. Justice, were it applied only to the individual, would be subjective and arbitrary and thus lead to disunity within a society. Also, I do not think it was necessary to mention the gods are just and therefore friends of the just men.
          Socrates’ final criticism of Thrasymachus’ point that injustice pays better than justice was that the just man is actually happier than the unjust man. Socrates began defining the function of a thing and used this to define the function of the mind. The mind’s function is life and the mind has its own specific excellence. Socrates used the agreement that “just was the particular excellence of the mind and injustice its defect” (Book I, 354e) to assume the “just mind and just man will have a good life, and the unjust a bad life.” (Book I, 354e) Since it never pays to be miserable, Socrates concludes that injustice never pays better than justice. In this way, Socrates dismembers Thrasymachus’ belief that the unjust man lives better than the just man. Personally, I believe that justice will make me happier than injustice, but who is to generalize this is the case for all humans? Some people surely take pleasure in doing others harm. Tyrants, to reiterate Thrasymachus’ belief, take pleasure in their wealth and power that is gained from taking from the people of the state. I do not think justice has anything to do with happiness and I think it is impossible to generalize just acts make people happier than unjust ones.

4.      I do not fully agree with Glaucon and Adeimantus. Glaucon, using the example of the invisibility ring, stated that both a just and unjust man would steal, murder, or seduce whenever it pleased them to do so if they had no fear of detection. I do agree that laws restrict what a man does and lead him to act more justly out of fear of punishment; however, I believe some people genuinely feel bad about committing unjust acts and their consciences will overpower the want to gain or harm. Socrates would favor my assertion that the heart of the just man stems from his good conscience not at the fear of punishment. I also agree that injustice pays better than justice in the extreme cases within these specific societies provided by Glaucon. Isolation and detest from a society when the man has done nothing unjust proves to me that the society is unjust and therefore a revolution should occur. Justice, as I see it, can only exist in a society; it is the generally agreed upon moral right and this is enforced by laws to restrict unjust acts. The moral rights stem from the people’s consciences. Without the concept of justice in a society, anarchy would ensue, and on this point I agree with Glaucon.
           I thus disagree with Adeimantus’ criticism of justice that people must have pure intentions in order to be just, because all the essentially matters is external actions because justice only lives in a society. Injustice should be punished and justice should be rewarded in order to have a successful society, Socrates would argue. Injustice applies to unjust acts, for if a man has unjust intentions but nothing shows externally of them, then it does not harm anyone and thus cannot be punished. Justice, similarly, applies to just acts, for if a man has just intentions but has actions deemed unjust by the society, then the man must be punished. If a man acts justly because he wishes to bolster his good reputation then I deem that perfectly acceptable. If a man acts justly because he genuinely wishes the betterment of others and in no way the betterment of himself, then I deem that acceptable although unbelievable. Just acts always seem to better oneself and Socrates would agree with me because it was he who stated “it never pays to be miserable, but to be happy.” (Book I, 354a) Thus, Socrates concurs that living a just life benefits the just man because it makes him happy and humans strive for happiness in life. The intentions lying underneath just acts are not relevant and thus I disagree with Adeimantus criticism of justice. 

No comments:

Post a Comment